Equality of outcome

Equality of outcome, equality of condition, or equality of results is a controversial[1] political concept. Although it is not always clearly defined, it is usually taken to describe a state in which people have approximately the same material wealth or, more generally, in which the general conditions of their lives are similar. Achieving this requires reducing or eliminating material inequalities between individuals or households in a society. This could involve a transfer of income and/or wealth from wealthier to poorer individuals, or adopting other institutions designed to promote equality of condition from the start. The concept is central to some political ideologies and is used regularly in political discourse, often in contrast to the term equality of opportunity. A related way of defining equality of outcome is to think of it as "equality in the central and valuable things in life."[2]

Contents

Comparisons with related concepts

Equality of outcome is often compared to related concepts of equality. Generally, the concept is most often contrasted with the concept of equality of opportunity, but there are other concepts as well. The term has been seen differently from differing political perspectives, but of all of the terms relating to equality, equality of outcome is the most "controversial" or "contentious".[1]

Political philosophy

In political philosophy, there are differing views whether equal outcomes are beneficial or not. One view is that there is a moral basis for equality of outcome, but that means to achieve such an outcome can be malevolent. Equality of outcome can be a good thing after it has been achieved since it reflects the natural "interdependence of citizens in a highly organized economy" and provides a "basis for social policies" which foster harmony and good will, including social cohesion and reduced jealousy. One writer suggested greater socioeconomic equality was "indispensable if we want to realise our shared commonsense values of societal fairness."[17] Analyst Kenneth Cauthen in his 1987 book The Passion for Equality suggested that there were moral underpinnings for having equal outcomes because there is a common good––which people both contribute to and receive benefits from––and therefore should be enjoyed in common; Cauthen argued that this was a fundamental basis for both equality of opportunity as well as equality of outcome.[18] Analyst George Packer, writing in the journal Foreign Affairs, argued that "inequality undermines democracy" in the United States partially because it "hardens society into a class system, imprisoning people in the circumstances of their birth."[19] Packer elaborated that inequality "corrodes trust among fellow citizens" and compared it to an "odorless gas which pervades every corner" of the nation.[19]

An opposing view is that equality of outcomes is not beneficial overall for society since it dampens motivation necessary for humans to achieve great things, such as new inventions, intellectual discoveries, and artistic breakthroughs. According to this view, wealth and income is a reward needed to spur such activity, and with this reward removed, then achievements which would benefit everybody may not happen.

If equality of outcomes is seen as beneficial for society, and if people have differing levels of material wealth in the present, then methods to transform a society towards one with greater equality of outcomes is problematic. A mainstream view is that mechanisms to achieve equal outcomes––to take a society and with unequal wealth and force it to equal outcomes––are fraught with moral as well as practical problems since they often involve force to compel the transfer.[18]

And there is general agreement that outcomes matter. In one report in Britain, unequal outcomes in terms of personal wealth had a strong impact on average life expectancy, such that wealthier people tended to live seven years longer than poorer folk, and that egalitarian nations tended to have fewer problems with societal issues such as mental illness, violence, teenage pregnancy, and other social problems.[20] Authors of the book The Spirit Level contended that "more equal societies almost always do better" on other measures, and as a result, striving for equal outcomes can have overall beneficial effects for everybody.[20]

Philosopher John Rawls, in his A Theory of Justice (1971), developed a "second principle of justice" that economic and social inequalities can only be justified if they benefit the most disadvantaged members of society. Further, Rawls claims that all economically and socially privileged positions must be open to all people equally. Rawls argues that the inequality between a doctor's salary and a grocery clerk's is only acceptable if this is the only way to encourage the training of sufficient numbers of doctors, preventing an unacceptable decline in the availability of medical care (which would therefore disadvantage everyone). Analyst Paul Krugman writing in The New York Times agreed with Rawls' position in which both equality of opportunity and equality of outcome were linked, and suggested that "we should try to create the society each of us would want if we didn’t know in advance who we’d be."[21] Krugman favored a society in which hard-working and talented people can get rewarded for their efforts but in which there was a "social safety net" created by taxes to help the less fortunate.[21]

Comparing equalities: outcome vs opportunity

Both equality of outcome and equality of opportunity have been contrasted to a great extent. When evaluated in a simple context, the more preferred term in contemporary political discourse is equality of opportunity which the public, as well as individual commentators, see as the nicer or more "well-mannered"[14] of the two terms.[22] And the term equality of outcome is seen as more controversial which connotes socialism or possibly communism and is viewed skeptically. A mainstream political view is that the comparison of the two terms is valid, but that they are somewhat mutually exclusive in the sense that striving for either type of equality would require sacrificing the other to an extent, and that achieving equality of opportunity necessarily brings about "certain inequalities of outcome."[8][23] For example, striving for equal outcomes might require discriminating between groups to achieve these outcomes; or striving for equal opportunities in some types of treatment might lead to unequal results.[23] Policies that seek an equality of outcome often require a deviation from the strict application of concepts such as meritocracy, and legal notions of equality before the law for all citizens. 'Equality seeking' policies may also have a redistributive focus.

The two concepts, however, are not always cleanly contrasted, since the notion of equality is complex. Some analysts see the two concepts not as polar opposites but as highly related such that they can not be understood without considering the other term. One writer suggested it was unrealistic to think about equality of opportunity in isolation, without considering inequalities of income and wealth.[17] Another agreed that it is impossible to understand equality without some assessment of outcomes.[14] A third writer suggested that trying to pretend that the two concepts were "fundamentally different" was an error along the lines of a conceit.[20]

In contemporary political discourse, of the two concepts, equality of outcome has sometimes been criticized as the "politics of envy" and is often seen as more "controversial" than equality of opportunity.[14] One wrote that "equality of opportunity is then set up as the mild-mannered alternative to the craziness of outcome equality."[14] One theorist suggested that an over-emphasis on either type of equality can "come into conflict with individual freedom and merit."[18] The philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche did not like either type of equality and was opposed in principle to democracy, and he associated equality with what he termed "slave morality."[18]

Critics of equality of opportunity note that while it is relatively easier to deal with unfairness for people with different races or genders, it is much harder to deal with social class since "one can never entirely extract people from their ancestry and upbringing."[24] As a result, critics contend that efforts to bring fairness by equal opportunity are stymied by the difficulty of people having differing starting points at the beginning of the socio-economic competition. A person born into an upper-middle class family will have greater advantages by the mere fact of birth than a person born into poverty.[24]

One newspaper account criticized discussion by politicians on the subject of equality as "weasely", and thought that terms using the word were politically correct and bland. Nevertheless, when comparing equality of opportunity with equality of outcome, the sense was that the latter type was "worse" for society.[25] Equality of outcome may be incorporated into a philosophy that ultimately seeks equality of opportunity. Moving towards a higher equality of outcome (albeit not perfectly equal) can lead to an environment more adept at providing equality of opportunity by eliminating conditions that restrict the possibility for members of society to fulfill their potential. For example, a child born in a poor, dangerous neighborhood with poor schools and little access to healthcare may be significantly disadvantaged in his attempts to maximize use of talents, no matter his work ethic. Thus, even proponents of meritocracy may promote some level of equality of outcome in order to create a society capable of truly providing equality of opportunity.

While outcomes can usually be measured with a great degree of precision, it is much more difficult to measure the intangible nature of opportunities. That is one reason why many proponents of equal opportunity use measures of equality of outcome to judge success. Analyst Anne Phillips argued that the proper way to assess the effectiveness of the hard-to-measure concept of equality of opportunity is by the extent of the actual and easier-to-measure equality of outcome.[14] Nevertheless, she described single criteria to measure equality of outcome as problematic: the metric of "preference satisfaction" was "ideologically loaded" while other measures such as income or wealth were insufficient, according to her view, and she advocated an approach which combined data about resources, occupations, and roles.[14]

To the extent that incidental inequalities can be passed from one generation to another through substantial gifts and wealth inheritance, some claim that equality of opportunity for children cannot be achieved without greater equality of outcome for parents. Moreover, access and opportunity to various social institutions is partially dependent on equality of outcome. Proponents argue that rigging equality of outcome can be a force preventing co-optation of non-economic institutions important to social control and policy formation, such as the legal system, media or the electoral process, by individuals and coalitions of wealthy people.

Greater equality of outcome is likely to reduce relative poverty, purportedly leading to a more cohesive society. However, if taken to an extreme it may lead to greater absolute poverty if it negatively affects a country's GDP by damaging workers' sense of work ethic by destroying incentives to work harder. Critics of equality of outcome believe that it is more important to raise the standard of living of the poorest in absolute terms. Some critics additionally disagree with the concept of equality of outcome on philosophical grounds .

A related argument is often encountered in education and more specifically in the debates on the grammar school in the United Kingdom and in the debates on gifted education in various countries. According to that argument, people by nature have differing levels of ability and initiative which lead some to achieve better outcomes than others. Therefore, it is considered impossible to ensure equality of outcome without imposing inequality of opportunity.

The concept in political argument

The concept of equality of outcome is an important one in battling between differing political positions, since the concept of equality, overall, was seen as positive and an important foundation which is "deeply embedded in the fabric of modern politics."[8] There is much political jousting over what, exactly, equality means.[8] It is not a new phenomenon; battling between so-called haves and have-nots has happened throughout human civilization, and was a focus of philosophers such as Aristotle in his treatise Politics. Analyst Julian Glover in The Guardian wrote that equality challenged both left-leaning and right-leaning positions, and suggested that the task of left-leaning advocates is to "understand the impossibility and undesirability of equality" while the task for right-leaning advocates was to "realise that a divided and hierarchical society cannot – in the best sense of that word – be fair."[26]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b Mark E. Rushefsky (2008). "Public Policy in the United States: At the Dawn of the Twenty-First Century". M. E. Sharpe Inc.. http://books.google.com/books?id=C3WF8anbYsIC&pg=PA36&dq=equality+of+outcome+vs+equality+of+opportunity#v=onepage&q&f=false. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(page 36) ... The third meaning of equality is the most controversial, equality of outcome or results. Here the emphasis is on social equality through programs such as affirmative action and progressive income taxes. While political equality and equality of opportunity are widely held values in American society, equality of outcome has been contentious." 
  2. ^ a b "Equality Impact Assessments". Hull Teaching Primary Care. 2011-07-15. http://www.hullpct.nhs.uk/impact_assessments/. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "Equality of autonomy - that is, equality in the degree of empowerment people have to make decisions affecting their lives, how much choice and control they have given their circumstances." 
  3. ^ Nicole Richardt, Torrey Shanks (2008). "Equal Opportunity". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. http://www.encyclopedia.com/topic/Equal_Opportunity.aspx. Retrieved 2011-09-12. "via Encyclopedia.com" 
  4. ^ "equal opportunity". Collins English Dictionary. 2003. http://www.thefreedictionary.com/equal+opportunity. Retrieved 2011-09-12. "the offering of employment, pay, or promotion equally to all, without discrimination as to sex, race, colour, disability, etc." 
  5. ^ "equal opportunity". Princeton University. 2008. http://www.thefreedictionary.com/equal+opportunity. Retrieved 2011-09-12. "(thesaurus) equal opportunity - the right to equivalent opportunities for employment regardless of race or color or sex or national origin" 
  6. ^ Carol Kitman (2011-09-12). "equal opportunity". Merriam-Webster Dictionary. http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/equal%20opportunity. Retrieved 2011-09-12. "nondiscrimination in employment esp. as offered by an equal opportunity employer -- : a context in which there is no discrimination esp. with regard to sex, race, or social standing <alcoholism has become an equal opportunity disease — Carol Kitman>" 
  7. ^ "equal opportunity". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (Houghton Mifflin). 2009. http://www.thefreedictionary.com/equal+opportunity. Retrieved 2011-09-12. "Absence of discrimination, as in the workplace, based on race, color, age, gender, national origin, religion, or mental or physical disability" 
  8. ^ a b c d e f Ed Rooksby (14 October 2010). "The complexity of equality: Equality for the left is a complex concept, which bears little resemblance to the caricatures drawn by the right". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2010/oct/14/complexity-of-equality. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "... "equality of outcome" which, as every Telegraph journalist knows, is a Bad Thing and, anyway, "impossible". ..." 
  9. ^ Paul de Vries (2011-09-12). "equal opportunity". Blackwell Reference. http://www.blackwellreference.com/public/tocnode?id=g9780631233176_chunk_g97814051001378_ss1-15. Retrieved 2011-09-12. "his standard has been used to define fairness in lending, housing, hiring, wage and salary levels, job promotion, voting rights ..." 
  10. ^ John W. Gardner (1984). "Excellence: Can we be equal and excellent too?". Norton. ISBN 0-393-31287-9. http://books.google.com/books?id=liE59woX624C&pg=PA46&dq=%22equality+of+opportunity%22&hl=en&ei=QBxqTqTfLeLv0gG27byuCQ&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=2&ved=0CDAQ6AEwATge#v=onepage&q=%22equality%20of%20opportunity%22&f=false. Retrieved 2011-09-08. "(see page 47)..." 
  11. ^ Mark E. Rushefsky (2008). "Public Policy in the United States: At the Dawn of the Twenty-First Century". M. E. Sharpe Inc.. http://books.google.com/books?id=C3WF8anbYsIC&pg=PA36&dq=equality+of+outcome+vs+equality+of+opportunity#v=onepage&q&f=false. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(page 36) ... A second meaning of equality is equality of opportunity, giving each person the right to develop to his or her potential. This is a procedural value: As long as no one is discriminated against, then the outcomes of achievement are of little concern. The third meaning of equality is the most controversial, equality of outcome or results. Here the emphasis is on social equality through programs such as affirmative action and progressive income taxes. ..." 
  12. ^ Sunder Katwala (21 October 2010). "It's equality of life chances, not literal equality, that the left espouses". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2010/oct/21/equality-life-chances-not-literal-left. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "Mostly, the modern democratic liberal-left argues for more equal life chances. Amartya Sen calls this equality of autonomy: that the ability and means to choose our life course should be spread as equally as possible across society. Clearly, it would then be pointless to eradicate every difference that resulted." 
  13. ^ Todd May (2008). "The political thought of Jacques Rancière: creating equality". The Pennsylvania State University Press. http://books.google.com/books?id=JJYjY8sG85kC&pg=PA19&lpg=PA19&dq=%22equality+of+autonomy%22#v=onepage&q=%22equality%20of%20autonomy%22&f=false. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(equality of autonomy) Amartya Sen has developed a theory of distributive justice that, like Rawls', requires the active intervention of institutions like the state into people's lives, but like Nozick's, aims that intervention at the fostering of people's self-creation rather than their living conditions. For Sen, the proper focus of a theory of justice is on what he calls capabilities, and he defines those capabilities on the basis of what he calls functionings." 
  14. ^ a b c d e f g h Anne Phillips (2004). "Defending Equality of Outcome". Journal of Political Philosophy. pp. 1–19. http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/533/. Retrieved 2011-07-15. 
  15. ^ "Equality Impact Assessments". Hull Teaching Primary Care. 2011-07-15. http://www.hullpct.nhs.uk/impact_assessments/. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(NHS Hull was created in October 2006 following the reconfiguration of Eastern and West Hull Primary Care Trusts.)Equality of process - dealing with inequalities in treatment through discrimination by other individuals and groups, or by institutions and systems, including not being treated with dignity and respect." 
  16. ^ a b "Equality, the goal not the signpost". Sociology. 27 April 2008. http://anthologyoi.com/sociology/equality-of-outcome-equality-of-oportunity.html. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "There are three forms of equality: equality of outcome, of opportunity, and of perception. Equality of perception is the most basic: it dictates that for people to be equal, each person should be perceived as being of equal worth. Equality of opportunity dictates that all people should have the same opportunities open to them if they put out the effort – this is a central tenet of the “American Dream.” The final form of equality, equality of outcome, attempts to “level the playing field” by forcing people into certain roles and dictates that all individuals should tend towards the mean – this form of equality is evident in socialist theory." 
  17. ^ a b c Martin O'Neill (12 October 2010). "Talk of fairness is hollow without material equality: Greater socioeconomic equality is indispensable if we want to realise our shared commonsense values of societal fairness". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2010/oct/12/fairness-is-hollow-without-equality. Retrieved 2011-07-15. 
  18. ^ a b c d Kenneth Cauthen (1987). "The Passion for Equality". Rowman & Littlefield. http://books.google.com/books?id=uH4D-XJox-0C&pg=PA57&dq=equality+of+outcome+vs+equality+of+opportunity#v=snippet&q=%22equality%20of%20outcome%22&f=false. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(page 136) There is a common good to which we contribute and from which we receive as members of a common system...." 
  19. ^ a b George Packer (November 2011). "The Broken Contract". Foreign Affairs. "Volume 90, Number 6 (see pages 29 and 31)" 
  20. ^ a b c d Bagehot (Aug 19th 2010). "On equality: The lessons of the Spirit Level debate for the left, the right and the British public". The Economist. http://www.economist.com/node/16844516. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "...The book’s authors, Richard Wilkinson and Kate Pickett, seek to show that “more equal societies almost always do better”. The two academics compare levels of mental illness, violence, teenage pregnancy and other social problems across various rich countries. Egalitarian places such as Scandinavia outperform highly stratified ones, including Britain." 
  21. ^ a b Paul Krugman (January 11, 2011). "More Thoughts on Equality of Opportunity". The New York Times. http://krugman.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/01/11/more-thoughts-on-equality-of-opportunity/. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "My vision of economic morality is more or less Rawlsian: we should try to create the society each of us would want if we didn’t know in advance who we’d be...." 
  22. ^ Lexington (Jul 7th 2011). "Fat cats and corporate jets: Why is it so unrewarding for politicians to bash the rich in America?". The Economist. http://www.economist.com/node/18928384. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "The point here is only that Americans do not seem to mind about the widening inequality of income and wealth as much as you might expect them to in current circumstances. ..." 
  23. ^ a b Edward Seidman, Julian Rappaport (editors) (1986). "Redefining social problems". Plenum Press. http://books.google.com/books?id=sDtMoSq93gAC&pg=PA292&dq=equality+of+outcome+vs+equality+of+opportunity#v=onepage&q&f=false. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(page 292+) Conflict 3: Equal Opportunity versus Equality of Outcome ... By emphasizing on principle, the other conflicting one may have to be sacrificed." 
  24. ^ a b Phillip Blond and John Milbank (27 January 2010). "No equality in opportunity: By synthesising old Tory and traditional left ideas a genuinely egalitarian society can be achieved". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2010/jan/27/inequality-opportunity-egalitarian-tory-left. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "But the ­rhetoric of egalitarian opportunity means that ­everyone who doesn't succeed is defined as a failure. Such contempt ­reinforces and repeats inequality. Why incoherent? Because where opportunity displaces outcome, the accident of birth is treated as if it was entirely analogous to the accident of race or gender. But it is not. Society and government can refuse race or gender prejudice simply by not being prejudicial. But class is not so easy: one can never entirely extract people from their ancestry and upbringing." 
  25. ^ Lucy Mangan (20 November 2010). "This week: Theresa May, Prince William and Kate Middleton and the Arnolds". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/theguardian/2010/nov/20/this-week-theresa-may-prince-william. Retrieved 2011-07-15. ""Equality", you see, is a weaselly, politically correct word that means either nothing or, worse, "equality of outcome". Imagine. From now on, we are going to have "fairness" and equality of opportunity. Trust her. It's the best of all possible worlds." 
  26. ^ a b Julian Glover (10 October 2010). "The left should recognise that equality is undesirable: It sounds horribly rightwing, but a fair society may be one in which people have the right to strive for inequality". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2010/oct/10/left-equality-fair-society-rightwing. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "In the early days of New Labour it is said a media adviser whispered into an ambitious minister's ear after an interview: "We don't say equality, we say fairness." The former reeked of socialism – all taxes, empowerment schemes and regulation. The latter was as inoffensive as a scented candle. Everyone can agree to be fair – which is the problem." 
  27. ^ a b Glenn Oliver. "What is the difference between Liberalism and Socialism ? I'd appreciate general rather than party political answers.". The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/notesandqueries/query/0,5753,-18035,00.html. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "Conservatives believe in inequality of opportunity and inequality of outcome. Liberals believe in equality of opportunity and inequality of outcome. Socialists believe in inequality of opportunity and equality of outcome." 
  28. ^ Andrew Chadwick (editor) Richard Heffernan (editor) Gordon Brown (author) (2003). "The new Labour reader -- Equality -- Then and Now". Polity Press. http://books.google.com/books?id=TXtZyi2IXNsC&pg=PA134&dq=equality+of+outcome+vs+equality+of+opportunity#v=onepage&q=%22equality%20of%20outcome%22&f=false. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "(page 111:) In the past, the promotion of social justice was sometimes confused with the imposition of equality of outcome." 
  29. ^ Kevin Boyle (July 18, 2010). "James T. Patterson's "Freedom Is Not Enough," reviewed by Kevin Boyle". The Washington Post. http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2010/07/16/AR2010071602877.html. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "Moynihan drafted his report in hopes of advancing the nation's racial agenda. By early 1965 African Americans had finally shattered the Southern system of segregation. But securing civil rights was only a first step, he argued. Now it was time to address the economic injustice that kept almost half the black population below the poverty line, to turn equality of opportunity into equality of outcome." 
  30. ^ Mark Penn (January 31, 2011). "How Obama can find his center". Washington Post. http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2011/01/31/AR2011013105146.html. Retrieved 2011-07-15. "The fundamental principle of centrism in the 1990s was that people would neither be left to fend for themselves nor guaranteed equality of outcome - they would be given the tools they needed to achieve the American dream if they worked hard. This central value can and should drive a lot more policies that people need and that work to resolve some of today's problems."